What Replaces the "Free Market" in an Egalitarian Sharing Economy? It's NOT a Centrally Planned Economy!
Marxists who say "If you want to ditch capitalism you need to embrace a centrally planned economy" are WRONG!
This is about how an economy that is not based on money works, without being a centrally planned economy. And yes, there is private property in such an economy, as discussed here.
The egalitarian sharing economy as described in Thinking about Revolution and here is based on sharing, according to need or reasonable desire, among those who contribute to the economy reasonably according to ability, with scarce things equitably rationed according to need. Critics of this kind of economy argue that it is either a Soviet-style centrally planned economy or, at any rate, it suffers from the same fatal faults as a centrally planned economy. They assert that when it comes to making an economy work properly, nothing can replace the discipline imposed by the free market in a capitalist economy.
Defenders of capitalism argue that the only way to ensure that the economic activity of people actually provides the products and services that consumers want, in an efficient manner, is by allowing the free market to guide economic decision-making by disciplining businesses with the threat that if they don't provide what customers want, at a price customers are willing to pay, efficiently enough to make a profit while doing this, then they will go out of business.
The beauty of discipline imposed by the free market, in this view, is that it requires no central planning board to determine if a business is providing what customers actually want, or if it is doing it efficiently enough to be permitted to operate. The problem with a centrally planned economy, according to this view, is that it is impossible for any central body to possess all of the vast information required to make all of the zillions of decisions that must be made in operating the economy of a nation rationally. This criticism of centrally planned economies is perfectly valid.
The question then is whether there is a way for an economy based on sharing and equality (no rich and no poor) that is neither centrally planned nor disciplined by a capitalist free market to "deliver the goods." What follows is an argument for the "Yes" answer to this question. One reason why this “Yes” answer is important is that some people—especially Marxists—argue that the answer is “No” and that therefore the only way to have a productive economy that is not a capitalist one is indeed to have it be centrally planned, with all of the anti-democratic features that are required to impose central planning—features that were so evident in the Soviet Union.
The Political Context of a Sharing Economy: Revolutionary Democracy
First, we need to recall what the political context is for a sharing economy. It is revolutionary democracy [a.k.a. voluntary federation of egalitarians, discussed here.] Revolutionary democracy [after this was written I began using the word "egalitarianism" instead of "revolutionary democracy" or "democratic revolution"; they all mean the same thing] means that the people who support the principles of equality and mutual aid ("egalitarians") hold power in society, and the people who oppose those principles do not.
Furthermore, it means that egalitarians use voluntary federation to achieve social order and coordinate things and cooperate with each other on a large scale, rather than authorizing a central government to dictate laws, as is the practice of today's so-called "democracies" as well as Communist governments. (The so-called "democracies" of today legitimize the dictatorial power of the central government by arguing "they were elected"; the Communist regimes (China and Cuba and North Korea) argue that the Party must rule for the good of the people until some time in the far distant future when people will be socially engineered in such a manner as to make society classless and cause the state to "whither away.")
Voluntary federation means that the only laws that people in a local community must obey are laws made by its local assembly, at which all egalitarians (but not people who oppose egalitarianism) in that community* have the right to participate as equals. Local assemblies send delegates to meet with delegates from other local assemblies (forming a non-local assembly of delegates), and these delegates craft proposals (not laws!) that are only implemented when sufficient numbers of local assemblies voluntarily agree to implement them, typically after a process of amendments being suggested by local assemblies and amendments being made by the assembly of their delegates.
Likewise, non-local assemblies (of delegates) send delegates in turn to meet with others like them from other regions to craft proposals for larger regions. And these assemblies may send delegates to yet "higher" level assemblies, etc. In this manner there can even be assemblies of delegates from all over the planet making proposals for globally coordinated efforts. But local assemblies (of egalitarian people living in the same community) only implement a proposal if they voluntarily wish to. There is no central government making laws that everybody is required to obey.**
One of the most important ways for local assemblies to cooperate with each other is to mutually agree to form a single sharing economy. In a sharing economy, there is no money; one is either a member of the sharing economy or not. If one is a member of the sharing economy then one enjoys the right, equal to all other members, to take (for free--there is no money) products and services that one needs or reasonably desires, or--in the case of things that are in short supply--to have a chance, equal to others with a similar need, to obtain these by an equitable rationing method determined by the local assembly.
If one is not a member of the sharing economy (it's voluntary and some may choose not to be) then one (or one's family or a group of people) may have whatever means of production they need (land, tools, etc.) to democratically (as equals with nobody being paid a wage or being enslaved) use those means of production to produce whatever they want, however they want, for their own use or to barter with individuals or economic enterprises in the sharing economy. If they don't want to do this either, then they are essentially a beggar. The ultimate authority that determines if one who wishes to be a member is or is not a member of the sharing economy is the local assembly for the community in which one resides.
The local assembly may, if it wishes, allow somebody to be a member of the sharing economy for any reason it wishes, but it also has the right to deny memberhsip to a person who does not contribute to the economy reasonably according to ability, as judged by the local assembly. Obviously, what constitutes a reasonable contribution according to ability would take into account a person's age and health and everything else that reasonable people would consider relevant.
Replace Profit With Reputation
Now we can address the question of what, in a sharing economy, takes the place of the free market in a capitalist economy. What, in other words, ensures that economically sensible activity is promoted and economically non-sensible activity is discouraged? In a free market capitalist economy it is profitability (or the lack thereof) that supposedly does this job. It does indeed discipline people in the economy, and it does indeed drive some businesses out of business that, from a reasonable point of view, ought to be driven out of business.
But a business can be profitable by catering to the very rich, thus directing economic resources towards producing things or services (e.g., psychiatry for a rich person's pet dog, a twenty-million dollar mansion for one small family) that are not terribly important at the cost of depriving others of things that are (e.g., health care, housing.) Profit is the reason why landowners don't grow food for people too poor to buy it, and instead grow crops that get made into luxury items that wealthy people can afford to buy. This is one reason capitalism is not good. In particular, this shows that in looking for something to replace profitability in a free market we are looking to replace something that is far from perfect to begin with. It is not necessary, therefore, for the replacement to be perfect, just better, as judged by criteria we think are important.
What are these important criteria? The following seem reasonable objectives for whatever replaces profitablity in a free market: 1) Promote economic activity that provides for the needs and desires of people living as equals in an egalitarian society. 2) Motivate people to contribute reasonably to the economy according to ability. 3) Promote efficient (with respect to the previous criteria) use of human and material resources.
The sensible replacement for profitability in a free market capitalist economy is reputation (with respect to the above criteria, as described below) in a sharing economy. Here is how reputation plays this key role. (Read here how reputation once played this key role successfully in real life despite being impeded by a centralized economy and an anti-democratic government.)
A local assembly, call it Assembly A, has the option of saying, "We won't agree to our community being in a sharing economy that includes local community X." If X has a reputation for admitting lots of people into the sharing economy who don't actually contribute and share reasonably according to ability in the opinion of Assembly A, or if, in Assembly A's opinion, local community X contributes things that are unreasonably useless (or of inferior quality or of insufficient quantity or not delivered reasonably, or immoral even, etc. etc.) compared to things that they could otherwise contribute, then Assembly A may exercise this option. If other local assemblies also share Assembly A's opinion (i.e., for whatever reason, they don't want to be in a sharing economy with community X), then Assembly X, if it wishes to remain in and enjoy the great benefits of membership in a larger sharing economy, will have a strong motivation for making changes to ensure that it has a good reputation.
Having a good reputation (for contributing to the economy reasonably and efficiently and morally) plays a role in a sharing economy analogous to having a high rate of profit in a capitalist economy. A decline in reputation (analogous to profit in a market economy) leads eventually to exclusion from the sharing economy (analogous to bankruptcy in a market economy).
Like profitability in a capitalist economy, reputation in a sharing economy operates at all scales, from that of a hot dog vendor on the sidewalk to a multi-national corporation. Here is why.
A local community assembly would typically oversee a committee it appoints to decide if economic enterprises in the community should be members of the sharing economy, based on their reputation as described above. If an economic enterprise is a member of the sharing economy that means that it can take from the economy--for free--what it needs or reasonably desires to operate, and the workers in it can take from the economy--for free--what they need or reasonably desire (unless the local assembly objects to a specific worker for some reason), with scarce things equitably rationed according to need by a method determined by the local assembly. Note that the workers in an economic enterprise do not work for wages and there is no money used here at all. Also note that all the workers in an enterprise have equal status in democratically making decisions about that enterprise, consistent with laws and policies of the local assembly of egalitarians for the community where the enterprise is located.
The decision--whether an economic enterprise is or is not a member of the sharing economy--would be about the enterprise as a single entity, not about each individual worker in it. And the decision would be based on the overall reputation of the enterprise. A hospital, for example, would be judged on the basis of its overall reputation, not a close inspection of every person who works in it, much as today when a sick person decides on what hospital to use he or she goes by overall reputation of the hospital, which might include things such as whether the hospital is certified by the appropriate organization, etc.
In order to maintain its good reputation, a hospital (to take that as an example, but we could be talking about any other economic enterprise), would in turn want to ensure that its component entities (the emergency room, the intensive care unit, etc.) have good reputations. The hospital (meaning the hospital workers, acting democratically as equals, in a "hospital assembly", or more generally a "workplace assembly") decides who can be a worker at the hospital. If the hospital is a member of the sharing economy, then so are all of its workers. If, however, a section within the hospital, say the ER, has a sufficiently bad reputation, then the hospital would be motivated to dismiss the workers who are responsible for the bad reputation, in order to maintain the good reputation of the hospital and its membership in the sharing economy. Thus the role of reputation extends downward from the level of the local community assembly to the economic enterprises within the community and even to the individual workers in those enterprises.
In a community there may be economic enterprises of varying sizes, from a one-person hot dog vendor on the sidewalk to a large hospital or local branch of a multinational organization. In the case of hot dog vendors, it would be likely that all of them would join an association of hot dog vendors (or something similar) and this association would, as a single entity, seek membership in the sharing economy based on its reputation; it would also be concerned with the reputation of individual hot dog vendors for the same reason as discussed above in the case of a hospital.
In the case of a local branch of a multi-national organization, the local branch could gain membership in the sharing economy for itself alone the same way any other economic enterprise does, or it could obtain membership in the sharing economy by virtue of being part of the larger multi-national organization if that organization itself is a member of a sharing economy that includes the local community in question. The multi-national organization could seek membership in a sharing economy (that includes many local communities) by having a "higher level" assembly of delegates, one that contained as members all of the local assemblies in the sharing economy, grant it membership. (Note for clarity: an assembly, A, is a member of a "higher level" assembly, B, if it sends a delegate to assembly B, or it is a member of an assembly that, in turn, is a member of assembly B. Thus there may be many "steps" between a local assembly and a national or even global assembly that it is a member of. Also note that when a "higher level" assembly of delegates grants membership in its sharing economy to economic enterprise X, that means that it has determined that none of its member local assemblies has objected to X being a member of its sharing economy; if one or more local assemblies did object then they could announce that they would leave the sharing economy unless the membership of X were revoked.)
As discussed above in the case of a local assembly not agreeing to remain in a sharing economy that included local assembly X with a bad reputation, local assemblies have the option of not agreeing to remain in a sharing economy that includes a multi-national organization whose reputation they don't like. If only local assembly A objects to multi-national organization X then A's choice, in practice, is to leave the sharing economy or remain in it with X. But if lots of local assemblies object to X, then one or more relatively high level assemblies could threaten to leave the larger sharing economy and establish a smaller one of their own unless X was denied membership in the larger sharing economy. To avoid this, X would of course be motivated to ensure that it has a good reputation among as many local assemblies as possible; otherwise it would risk exclusion from a large sharing economy--the equivalent of going out of business in a capitalist economy. (If you're wondering how this could be handled in practice, please read the section below titled "A Boring Technical Detail" and the article it links to.)
Reputation thus plays an extremely important role in the sharing economy, a role similar to that played by profitability in a capitalist economy. Reputation in a sharing economy would be so important that some economic enterprises in a sharing economy would specialize in performing the function of deciding whether or not to grant their version of the "Goodhousekeeping Seal of Approval" or their version of what is today called "certification" for colleges, etc. Others might be more like newspapers that investigate wrongdoing (and excellence as well) and report it. It is impossible to anticipate all of the creative ways that reputations might be established for various kinds of economic enterprises. Who, for example, could have anticipated a few decades ago Facebook's "like" system? But one way or another, in a society in which reputation plays such an important role, ways will be invented for establishing reputations sensibly.
The striking advantage of reputation driving economic decision making in a sharing economy, in contrast to profit in a capitalist one, is that reputation is based on the most important criteria, whereas profit is not. Only when reputation, and not profit, drives decision-making is it possible for a local community assembly to make reasonableness prevail over unreasonableness, by, for example, denying membership in the sharing economy to a person or enterprise whose "contribution" is providing psychoanalysis for pet dogs, or constructing twenty-million dollar mansions for small families when this is at the expense of some people having far more important things, such as good health care or shelter.
But how would economic decisions actually be made based on reputation? How is it possible, practically speaking? Letting individual consumers make decisions by choosing how to spend their money has resulted in the remarkable entrepreneurship, creativity and productivity that capitalism claims for itself and for itself alone. Because the only sustained (at least more than a few years) modern challenge to free market capitalism--Soviet style central planning--has clearly failed, capitalism claims that, as Margaret Thatcher famously put it, There Is No Alternative. Doesn't decision-making by reputation instead of profit entail the same problems that make a centrally planned economy fail? Doesn't a reputation-based sharing economy suffer from the same two defects as a centrally planned economy: a) stifling entrepreneurship creativity and b) failing to make use of information scattered among huge numbers of people, information that is incorporated in the price of things in the market place? How is a reputation-based sharing economy, with respect to these key questions, any different from a centrally planned economy?
Entrepreneurship in the Sharing Economy
One important difference concerns entrepreneurship; it is suppressed in a centrally planned economy but promoted in a sharing economy. The reason for this stems from the difference between voluntary federation versus an authoritative central government. In the sharing economy (with voluntary federation) there is no central government, certainly not one making the zillions of economic decisions that a centralized planned economy entails. Unlike a centralized planned economy, people in the sharing economy, as individuals or larger groups, are free to, in fact encouraged to, be entrepreneurs, in the good sense of the word. Entrepreneurship, in the good sense (the "better mousetrap" sense), means thinking creatively about how to provide a much-loved new product or service, or a traditional one much more efficiently. The motive is not to get richer than others (as in capitalism), but the satisfaction of doing something wonderful and the enjoyment of the consequent respect and admiration from others for doing it. (Those who don't appreciate the power of this motive should read pages 14-15 in Thinking about Revolution, for starters; also The Capitalist Big Lie about Human Nature.)
In the sharing economy, a person or group of people with an entrepreneurial idea can "pitch" their idea as a proposal to the local community assembly, say Assembly A. If the proposal is approved as the basis for membership in the sharing economy of the enterprise and its workers, then the enterprise can take (for free) from the sharing economy everything it needs, and the workers, as members of the sharing economy, can take everything they reasonably need or wish, as described above.
Of course Assembly A's decision to approve or not would take into account the availability of relevant raw materials and manufactured items. If these things must come from other communities, then Assembly A would need to determine that their reputation will not be adversely affected by taking these things for the entrepreneur's project. To do this they might simply use their knowledge about how other people felt. But this runs the risk that they approve a project only to discover that other local assemblies object to it, adversely affecting Assembly A's reputation. Instead, Assembly A might have their delegate to the appropriate "higher level" assembly introduce a proposal for sharing the things that the entrepreneur's project requires and the things that the entrepreneur's project produces. This proposal would go through the process of being amended by other delegates; then, in the course of seeing if the local assemblies agreed, there might be suggested amendments from them, and back and forth negotiations until there was a proposal that sufficient assemblies agreed with to make the entrepreneur's project possible.
Before objecting that this process for an entrepreneur to get the green light to start his/her new enterprise is too restrictive or cumbersome, compare it to what a would-be entrepreneur must do in our current capitalist society. Unless a would-be entrepreneur is very wealthy, he or she needs to get wealthy people to loan or invest the big bucks required to start the new enterprise. This means going to venture capitalists or banks or appearing before the "sharks" on that T.V. show. It means trying to persuade rich people that they can get even richer by investing in or loaning money to one's proposed business. This too can be a restrictive or cumbersome process. Even worse is the fact that instead of having to persuade people that one's proposed enterprise will be good for ordinary people (as in egalitarianism), one must persuade rich people that it will make them even richer.
Reputation Embodies More Important Information than Market Place Price
Economic decision making as described above, which applies to both entrepreneurial and well-established enterprises, involves a huge number of people--possessing an enormous amount of information collectively---contributing directly or indirectly to the decision whether to give an economic project a green light. The knowledge of entrepreneurs, for example, is made use of far more than in a centrally planned economy that is hostile to creative ideas arising outside the central planning body.
Additionally, the knowledge and opinions of every person in any way affected by the decision to give or not give a green light (i.e., membership in the sharing economy) to an economic enterprise is tapped in one way or another because the decision is always made with great consideration paid to not damaging one's reputation in the eyes of all others affected by the decision. For example, a local assembly will think very hard about the effect on its reputation, among all of the people in all of the other local communities that are members of its sharing economy, that will result from any particular decision it makes about granting membership in its sharing economy to a particular economic enterprise; if it grants membership to a pet dog psychiatry enterprise this might result in lots of other local assemblies saying they refuse to be in the same sharing economy with it, with the consequences that are discussed above.
Furthermore, the criteria for a good reputation are the right criteria--the things that egalitarians (the only ones who can be members of a local community assembly) care about most, whereas the criterion of profit is a deeply flawed one. This means that the information gathered from large numbers of people for economic decision-making is not only vast in quantity but better in quality than the information incorporated into mere price in the market place. The sharing economy based on reputation for decision-making is thus both superior to a centrally planned economy and a market place capitalist economy based on profit.
A reputation-based sharing economy will certainly not be perfect.*** Perfection is an impossible goal. There is not, and never could be, a profit-based capitalist society in which every worker worked 100% efficiently and every business derived the maximum conceivable profit that the laws permit. Look closely anywhere today and one will find what, from the point of view of profitability, is inefficiency. From the point of view of human happiness and decency, however, what a capitalist calls inefficiency might often better be called reasonableness. Basing economic decisions on reputation (for reasonableness) is, arguably, the best way for reasonable people to make society reasonably good, which is to say a whole lot better than our present capitalist society.
Apologists for capitalism argue that only a free market capitalist society based on the profit motive will make possible the "creative destruction" and innovation that is required to produce better and better and more and more stuff. The ONLY basis for the pro-capitalism argument is the fact that, as illustrated by the Soviet Union, a centrally planned economy did not foster innovation as much as the free market did in the capitalist West at that time. But egalitarianism rejects a centrally planned economy.
Furthermore, who says that "creative destruction" and innovation and better and better and more and more stuff--as desirable as these may sometimes be (while also often causing great hardship to people by making them unemployed and in other ways well known to working class people in capitalist societies of class inequality)--is necessarily more important than other considerations people have regarding what makes for a good life in a good society?
In either event, the experience of egalitarian Spain in 1936-9 shows that an egalitarian economy outproduced the capitalist economy it replaced, as shown in some detail here. Sure, apologists for capitalism will argue that the egalitarians in Spain only worked hard to increase economic productivity because they were at war with the fascists, but if they had won that war then they would have stoped working so hard. To which I reply, perhaps that is true, but so what? Is the purpose of life only to work as hard as possible to produce as much stuff as possible?
A Boring Technical Detail
When a person in an egalitarian sharing economy goes into a "store" to obtain some commodity (or service), what actually happens, given that money is not used at all? To read about this, click here.
Another Boring Technical Detail
How do suppliers of proverbial "widgets" in an egalitarian sharing economy know how many widgets to produce? Typically, this question takes the form of whether they should produce more or produce less than the current amount being produced. The people who need or want the widgets are just as capable of communicating whether there are too few or too many widgets in an egalitarian sharing economy as they are of communicating this in a capitalist profit-driven economy. Human ingenuity in such matters is amazing. There is no reason to believe that in an egalitarian sharing economy widgets will either start piling up in unwanted piles for a long time, or that people will suffer widget deprivation for a long time. Things analogous to today's "on time delivery" would be perfectly possible in an egalitarian sharing economy. The purpose of the voluntary federation system, with its assemblies and delegates, is to address these problems by crafting proposals for mutual agreement. The culture of egalitarianism (mutual aid instead of competition to see who will be a winner and who a loser) makes such solutions desirable for everybody and hence very likely to be implemented.
Further Reading
"Which Creates a Higher Standard of Living: Capitalism or Egalitarianism?"
"Why Abolish the Use of Money?"
"The Transitional Phase to Egalitarianism"
Go here to learn about a real-life way that egalitarian people have been using a pseudo-market to equitably ration donated food sensibly: communities receive an allowance of "credits" based on the number of people in need of food, and the communities "buy" donated food with these "credits."
-----------------------------
* Here, in the context of who can participate in a local assembly, the phrase "in the community" means residing in the community or, in the case of a person who resides outside the community, working reasonably in an enterprise located in the community.
** Local assemblies can, however, cooperate to defend people who are attacked by anti-egalitarians. If, for example, people somewhere decided (democratically or not) to enslave others, then local assemblies of egalitarians would have every right to form a militia and forcibly prevent them from enslaving anybody. From the point of view of the would be slave owners, they would essentially be ordered by a "central government" (i.e., an authoritarian, top-down commanding government) to cease enslaving people. It is the egalitarians, not anti-egalitarians, who should enjoy the absence of such an authoritarian law-making central government.
*** Much of what passes for certification of things such as hospitals today is in fact bullshit; the certification organizations are often paid by the institutions they certify and therefore don't want to ruffle the feathers of those institutions too much with a certification inspection that truly aims to determine if the institution is performing at a high quality.
For example, the organization certifying a hospital nowadays will, when it makes its inspection, ask random employees of the hospital if they know what this or that acronym (related to, say, patient safety) stands for. The hospital, knowing (from the accrediting organization) that these acronyms are likely to be asked about, prepares for the inspection by making sure that employees know what the acronyms stand for. If a sufficiently high percentage of the employees answer the acronym question correctly, the hospital is judged to be doing a great job when it comes to, say, patient safety even though the employees may not have the foggiest notion about what should be done to ensure patient safety. This is a form of "you scratch my back, I'll scratch yours" corruption.
In our current society of class inequality, this kind of corruption is pervasive. The kind of people with the real power are the ones who have the capitalist value of self-interest, and the kind of people who are delegated power to do things such as certify institutions are the ones who know how to look the other way when corruption is going on rather than stand up for the public's welfare.
In an egalitarian society, in contrast, ordinary people who genuinely have the public's welfare as their concern can also have the real power to ensure that certification of (and newspaper reporting on) institutions is truly designed to give institutions a reputation that accurately indicates their quality of service or product.
John, can you show us something in the writing of Marx or his immediate disciples which insists upon a centrally planned economy? I do not think it exists.
Sir, you are in total denial about the essentials of human nature- Sin and selfishness.